dc.contributor.author | Garmendia Mugica, Joana | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2020-10-02T18:29:21Z | |
dc.date.available | 2020-10-02T18:29:21Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2006 | |
dc.identifier.citation | Gogoa 6(1) : 77-89 (2006) | |
dc.identifier.issn | 1577-9424 | |
dc.identifier.uri | http://hdl.handle.net/10810/46418 | |
dc.description.abstract | One o( the main debates in Pragmatics nowadays deals with the concept of what is said by an utterance (i.e., wl/ilt a speaker says by uttering a sentence). With regard to irony, the issue o( what is said is especially complicated: the problem is not to decide wlwt is exactly said hy an ironic utterance, but rather to clarify in ti/(' first place whether there is anything really said. Manyauthors llave proposed to replace wlwt is said hy a special concept in the analysis o( irony. But some costs are in volved: the speaker 's commitment, which is usually linked to what is said, loses its position in the pragmatic explanation o( uttemnce content; bcsides, the input for the implicaturcs nceds clarification, sinC(' the in(erence of implicatures is usually considered to start from wllat is said. I wi/l (¡CUS on thesc two problcms, showing tlwt some pragmatic assumptior/S should he rejected in arder to of(er a satisfactory answer. | |
dc.language.iso | eus | |
dc.publisher | Servicio Editorial de la Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatearen Argitalpen Zerbitzua | |
dc.rights | info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess | |
dc.title | Zer esan ironiaz | |
dc.type | info:eu-repo/semantics/article | |
dc.rights.holder | © 2006, Servicio Editorial de la Universidad del País Vasco Euskal Herriko Unibertsitateko Argitalpen Zerbitzua | |